Saturday, July 13, 2024

Reading Notes: July 13th, 2024

“The only thinker within the early Cartesian School who called in question the doctrine of representative perception was Arnauld. In his Traite des Vraies et Des Fausses Idees, which was written as a criticism of Malebranche’s Recherche de la Verite, he states in the most definite manner that there is no direct evidence of the existence of subjective states, acting as intermediaries between mind and matter, and that the sole (and on his view insufficient) ground for their assumption is (as we have already seen in the Chapter on Descartes’ problem) the local difference between object known and the brain through which it is known….Even the ground that objects cannot be known directly, since they are material and therefore wholly different from the immaterial mind, reduces to this one ground. For it is because the mind is unextended, that, even though it be locally present to a body, it still remains external to it. As Malebranche remarks, though the mind were to issue out of the body in order to visit the sun, being unextended, it could not contain that star within itself, and would therefore, even though it got inside it, still remain as external to it as one body is to another.” (Kemp Smith, Studies in the Cartesian Philosophy, 115-116)

“Sense and imagination are, therefore, [in Descartes philosophy] related to thought in the same way that figure and motion are related to extension, that is, as modes to their common attribute.” (Kemp Smith, Studies in the Cartesian Philosophy, 127)

“In [self-consciousness] we have experience of a unity that is capable of maintaining itself throughout the variety of its states, and of an activity that progressively unfolds that unity in the realisation of desire. Further, within the unity of each perception there is always involved a multiplicity, infinitely complex.” (Kemp Smith, Studies in the Cartesian Philosophy, 167)

“Materialism has on its side a formidable array of arguments from facts. It can point to certain and undeniable and invariable sequences of cause and effect. All sorts of disturbances and alterations of consciousness arise when poisons are introduced into the blood, from the excitement or stupor of intoxication to the profound coma of Bright’s disease. Again, my brain processes slacken down, and I pass into the unconsciousness of dreamless sleep. They are interfered with by the rupture of a blood vessel, and, either special departments of my consciousness are interfered with, or I lose consciousness altogether, or for so long as the interference lasts, that is to say, according to the extent and persistence of the lesion. My brain processes cease altogether, and—the inference seems too obvious to state. And yet the extreme conclusion does not follow unless materialism can show that physical processes give rise to consciousness in the first place. If they cannot, there will be no need to infer that their ceasing must cause its extinction.” (Sinclair, A Defense of Idealism, 76-77)

Friday, July 12, 2024

Reading Notes: July 12th, 2024

“The ignorant physicist sometimes says, “We know that there is matter. Why need we go further to an unknown something called mind?” But his very assertion is self-destructive. It implies the priority of the something knowing to the something known. He has not been able to assert matter without postulating mind. You not only can not prove matter, you can not define it, without implying the existence of mind.” (Krauth, The Strength and Weaknesses of Idealism, 294)

“The murder of matter is the suicide of mind.” (Krauth, The Strength and Weaknesses of Idealism, 301)

“No purely physiological investigation can explain the phenomena of consciousness….How it is that molecular changes in the brain cells coincide with modifications of consciousness; how, for instance, the vibrations of light falling on the retina excite the modification of consciousness termed a visual sensation, is a problem which cannot be solved. We may succeed in determining the exact nature of the molecular changes which occur in the brain cells when a sensation is experienced, but this will not bring us one whit nearer the explanation of the ultimate nature of that which constitutes the sensation. One is objective and the other subjective, and neither can be expressed in terms of the other. We cannot say that they are identical, or even that the one passes into the other; but only, as Laycock expresses it, that the two are correlated, or, with Bain, that the physical changes and the psychical modifications are the objective and subjective sides of a ‘double-faced unity’….The physiological activity of the brain is not, however, altogether co-extensive with its psychological functions. The brain as an organ of motion and sensation, or presentative consciousness, is a single organ composed of two halves; the brain as an organ of ideation, or re-presentative consciousness, is a dual organ, each hemisphere complete in itself. When one hemisphere is removed or destroyed by disease, motion and sensation are abolished unilaterally, but mental operations are still capable of being carried on in their completeness through the agency of the one hemisphere. The individual who is paralyzed as to sensation and motion by disease of the opposite side of the brain (say the right), is not paralyzed mentally, for he can still feel and will and think, and intelligently comprehend with the one hemisphere. If these functions are not carried on with the same vigour as before, they at least do not appear to suffer in respect of completeness.” (Ferrier, The Functions of the Brain, 256-257) 

“Davidson’s account of subjectivity (or ‘the subjective’) as first-person authority is, we believe, a cause of a philosopher simply being blind to subjectivity as a question in its own right. His point is that once we get rid of the idea of subjectivity as a ‘parade of objects before the mind’ (the Cartesian idea), all that remains is privacy and asymmetry, and these can be explained as a mere side effect of natural language in our minds. Whereas Davidson officially intends to account for ‘the subjective’, and in investigating the possibility of truth and objective knowledge for beings such as ourselves, sets out relating the objective, the intersubjective and the subjective, the fact is, his whole approach rests on the priority of a third-person perspective, and takes behavioural evidence as touchstone (even considering that the appeal to the intersubjective in his last writings aims at taking distance from Quinean-like behaviorism, itself undoubtably an even more radically third-personal approach). Still, Davidson’s overall view of subjectivity as first-person authority in linguistic creatures amounts to an elimination of subjectivity and a trivialization of the problem of self-knowledge.” (Miguens and Preyer, Are There Blindspots in Thinking About Consciousness and Subjectivity?, 13)

“Nature teaches me by these sensations of pain, hunger, thirst, etc., that I am not only lodged in my body as a pilot in a vessel, but that I am besides so intimately conjoined, and, as it were, intermixed with it, that my mind and body compose a certain unity. For if this were not the case I should not feel pain when my body is hurt, seeing I am merely a thinking thing, but should perceive the wound by the understanding alone, just as a pilot perceives by sight that part of his vessel is damaged.” (Descartes, Meditations, VI, 336)

Thursday, July 11, 2024

Reading Notes: July 11th, 2024

“If any system, whether under the influence of other objects or not, has been quiescent for a finite time it can only be through the action of external objects and not through its own nature that it ceases to be quiescent. Such a system will neither change its qualities nor move as a whole or in parts, nor cease to exist as a whole or in parts unless it is forced to do so by changes in objects external to it.” (Broad, Perception, Physics, and Reality: An Enquiry into the Information that Physical Science Can Supply About the Real, 85-86)

“The continuity of space is defined mathematically as an infinite series of points or positions, and therefore as absolutely discrete, and the infinity of the series is defined by the negation of contact. No member is next another and between any two points there is another. So also with the continuity of time the instants are points and the process succession, and the compactness of a period consists in no two instants being next one another so as to exclude an intervening instant.” (Carr, Symposium: The Quantum Theory: How Far Does it Modify the Mathematical, the Physical and the Psychological Concepts of Continuity?, 48-49)

Tuesday, July 9, 2024

Reading Notes: July 9th, 2024

“It is not, therefore, surprising that philosophers who have openly or tacitly subscribed to the metaphysical presuppositions of formal logic have been tireless in their efforts to find a justification for inductive generalization, or somehow extricate it from Hume’s criticism….The so-called pragmatic justification of induction, which claims that the procedure is vindicated by its ubiquitous success, fails, because, first, no attempt is ever made to demonstrate the prevalence of the alleged success. It is simply assumed that the triumph of empirical science is that of inductive reasoning because it is assumed that no other method is available. No investigation is made by those claiming this kind of justification for induction into the actual procedures adopted by practising scientists, and it has never been established that induction as traditionally described—inference from observed conjunction of particulars to the major recurrence of similar conjunctions—has ever been the source of major scientific discoveries. Secondly, however, even if it had, the argument from past success of the method as a justification of its future use is a petitio principii, because it invokes the very principle it is meant to justify.” (Harris, Formal, Transcendental, and Dialectical Thinking, 52-53)

“Sentience or feeling is the pervasive characteristic of mind, which persists at all levels and throughout its dialectical development. It is the matrix of all mental process—its “proximate matter” (to use an Aristotelian concept). But it is not yet cognition. Like the prior phases, of which it is the formal unity, and which are all dynamic processes, sentience too is a form of activity. It is the organism’s activity as felt—the active registration of the impingement upon it of its environment, its own reactivity to it. As such, it is internally diversified, but as felt it is a unified totality within which the differences have yet to be delineated. This requires ordered selection, differentiation, contrast, and interrelation of qualitative distincta. The activity by which sentience thus differentiates and organizes itself is a specialization of its own functioning, namely the discursive activity of attention, which singles out particular qualitative elements and sets them in context. The organic needs and impulses are its initial guides, causing it to focus on particular sense-contents in turn and to set each against a felt background, organizing the sentient field into a figure-and-ground structure, which is the minimum requirement for cognition, or perception.” (Harris, Formal, Transcendental, and Dialectical Thinking, 177)

“It is not easy to define psychologically or to identify the physiological counterpart of attention, but it cannot be regarded as a merely mechanical process of sorting and singling out. Although it has a character analogous to a searchlight directed and focused upon an object, and although terms appropriate to light are often used to describe its effect, it is no mere illumination, because it is cognitive. It does not merely reveal an object, it grasps and assimilates it. In fact, it virtually creates the so-called datum, for apart from its selectivity no cognizable object exists, only the indiscriminate conglomerate of primitive sentience. Attention is no merely passive unveiling, but is an active comprehending of the discriminated elements in their mutual relation. Accordingly, it is (or involves) incipient judgment. The datum it creates is a “somewhat” in contrast with another (somewhat else), and this contrast is cognized, or apprehended. It is an awareness, not simply of the single datum, but of that in relation to its background, or other. It is the apprehension and inchoate intellectual articulation of a structured whole.” (Harris, Formal, Transcendental, and Dialectical Thinking, 177)

“The principles of organization on which the sentient matrix is thus perceptually ordered so as to constitute objects of cognition are categories of concepts….The pure, indefinite, confused mass of feeling is qualitatively utterly indefinite. It is the mere “manifold of sense” of which Kant remarked that it is “as good as nothing.” It is likewise the equivalent of what Hegel called pure being and which he, too, identified with nothing. It is only in the discursus of mutually contrasted contents, of “this” distinguished from “that,” a figure on a ground, that perception of an object arises—perception of something definite in contrast to something else.” (Harris, Formal, Transcendental, and Dialectical Thinking, 177-178)

“This contraposition of figure and ground, of the object centered by attention against a less distinct background, or, within attention, of contrasted qualities and levels, is a cognition entirely dependent upon the mutual mediation of the moments. It is a dynamic process of comparison and contrast, an activity or motion which is not improperly identified as becoming. The object comes to be for consciousness in this movement, and without it…no object is cognized. The object…is created by attention, and attention is the concentrated focus of the discursive activity.” (Harris, Formal, Transcendental, and Dialectical Thinking, 178)

“Actuality is thus the integrated whole of the universe specifying itself as the self-differentiating space-time unity of the physical world which evolves to the self-differentiating biocoenosis of the biosphere…” (Harris, Formal, Transcendental, and Dialectical Thinking, 195)

“Knowledge is the object—the world—come to consciousness in the living organism, which in its organicism epitomizes the whole which it brings to consciousness. Knowledge, therefore, is from the first the self-consciousness of the object. It is the object aware of itself. Subject and object are thus ab origine identical; but they are also non-identical because the first is a higher phase in the dialectic through which the whole is realizing itself and has come to consciousness of itself. Hence, while it is itself of which it becomes aware, its awareness is a different and more adequate phase of itself than that of which it is aware, the immediately prior phase of its own dialectical development. In knowledge, the object (which is its own earlier phase) is sublated and transformed as self-consciousness. But this consciousness is not at first consciousness of self as object, but is consciousness of object as other than or nonidentical with self. In the first instance, then, it is inadequate to the completeness and coherence of the whole, which is dirempt in the opposition of object to subject.” (Harris, Formal, Transcendental, and Dialectical Thinking, 237-238)

“A magnitude is essentially one, not many. Thus no magnitude is correctly expressed as a number of terms….It is necessary, in order to obtain divisibility, to take the whole strictly as one, and to regard divisibility as its adjective….The whole has a certain relation, which for convenience we may call that of inclusion, to all its parts. This relation is the same whether there be many parts or few; what distinguishes a whole of many parts is that it has many such relations of inclusion. But it seems reasonable to suppose that a whole of many parts differs from a whole of few parts in some intrinsic respect.” (Russell, The Principles of Mathematics, 173)

Continuity applies to series (and only to series) whenever these are such that there is a term between any two given terms. Whatever is not a series, or a compound of series, of whatever is a series not fulfilling the above condition, is discontinuous. Thus the series of rational numbers is continuous, for the arithmetic mean of two of them is always a third rational number between the two. The letters of the alphabet are not continuous. We have seen that any two terms in a series have a distance, or a stretch which has magnitude. Since there are certainly discrete series (e.g., the alphabet), there are certainly discrete magnitudes, namely, the distances or the stretches of terms in discrete series. The distance between the letters and C is greater than that between the letters and B, but there is no magnitude which is greater than one of these and less than the other.” (Russell, The Principles of Mathematics, 173)

“As regards the realistic criticisms of Idealism, it seems necessary to conclude that not one is a valid criticism of Objective Idealism. In so far as they were intended to be such, they fail because they are based upon misconceptions of the meaning of Objective Idealism or because they involve faulty inferences….[Realism’s chief aim], “the refutation of idealism” or “the refutation of the monistic theory,” has not been achieved….As a result of the protests of the Realists, Objective Idealists have been led to define their position more carefully and to distinguish it more sharply from other types of Idealism.” (Hawes, The Logic of Contemporary English Realism, 58-59)

“[According to Russell] real or mathematical space is composed of an infinite number of points, and time of an infinite number of instants. Points are without extension, and instants without duration. Things are composed of extensionless, durationless elements which occupy only a point and an instant. The ultimate formal constituent of matter in physics is such a point-instant particle. Motion is the successive occupation of successive positions at successive times.” (Hawes, The Logic of Contemporary English Realism, 102)

“You cannot have truth except as reality in ideal form. And you cannot know reality except by apprehending the ideal form in its concrete spirit and all its detail. This does not mean that reality is qualified as or by a series of psychical events. The qualification of reality by ideas is from the beginning a qualification by meanings. This is the significance of thought, which is in its essence an effort to define the universe by meanings adequately conditioned; to reconstruct the unity of the real in ideal or discursive form.” (Bosanquet, Implication and Linear Inference, 149)

“First, my mind does not come to me as a separable source that judges by connecting particulars ab extra. It comes to me as a full world which reshapes itself by its own impulse, involving, as it does so in certain respects, more or less of a peculiar satisfaction which attends upon adequacy and coherency. So far from misrepresenting the world, my mind as a volitional and capricious being cannot in the least affect that reshaping by the world of its own meanings which is judgment….Further, my mind has nothing but the world’s reality to draw from; and, again, the world has no way of becoming ideally determinate but through it.” (Bosanquet, Implication and Linear Inference, 152)

“The extreme behaviorist frankly denies that what we mean by consciousness exists at all, and substitutes for the study of consciousness the study of the motions of the body and its parts. He rejects consciousness because there is no place in his system of materialistic mechanism for such a reality as conscious is experienced to be. Would it not be more reasonable to revise the system in light of experience than to reject experience on account of the demands of the system?” (Brightman, An Introduction to Philosophy, 273)

“Without the power to hold in mind at once events that take time, all temporal and all rational experience would be impossible. The mind, then, is temporal in that it experiences sequence and duration, but it is supertemporal in that it is able to grasp in a single conscious act a series of events that take time….No account of mind is complete or philosophically sound that considers the temporal features of mind without also considering its time-transcending features and the relations between the two. Mechanism, then, is inadequate.” (Brightman, An Introduction to Philosophy, 275)

“If the materialist still lives a wholesome, active, human life, his life has no logical connection with his philosophy. Like Hume, he forgets his speculations; and what is more, he lives as if they were not true….There is a double tragedy in the life of a good materialist: the tragedy of a worthless universe and the tragedy of self-contradiction between theory and life.” (Brightman, An Introduction to Philosophy, 363)

Monday, July 8, 2024

That Which Knows All Things and Is Known by None: An Argument Against the Identity Theory of Mind

“He sees, but he can’t be seen, he hears, but he can’t be heard; he thinks, but he can’t be thought of; he perceives, but he can’t be perceived.” 
Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upanishad, 3.7.23
Since its modern development over half a century ago, the Identity Theory of Mind has attracted criticism from various spheres of the philosophical scene. This paper is an addition to that ever-growing body of literature. However, the proceeding argument is unique in that it does not depend upon either (a) one’s acceptance, or non-acceptance, of the existence of “qualia,” (b) the fact of there so being, or not so being, “explanatory gaps” in the Identity Theorist’s account of consciousness, (c) the conceivability, or inconceivability, of “philosophical zombies,” (d) the physical world so having, or not so having, an “intrinsic nature,” or (e) the existence of facts about which a “brilliant color scientist” either did, or did not, come to know. Whether or not the argument succeeds, I hope that it may give rise to new directions of discourse in the unbounded field of philosophical inquiry.1

The Principle of Perceptual Determinacy

The world unfolds itself for us conscious beings through communions of perceivings and perceiveds: perceptual states and their percepta. These distinguishable factors march two abreast, side-by-side, hand-in-hand, as mutually-implying correlates within a subject’s experience. For a subject to “perceive” a tree is for him to “have” a perceptual state that is a “perception of a tree;”2 thus, if a subject has a perceptual state, P, and P is a “perception of a tree,” then P’s perceptum is that tree which the subject perceives—that particular “somewhat” which P is a “perception of.”3

Whenever a subject perceives, the perceptum of his perceptual state is an existing, or occurring, determinate “somewhat.” Moreover, this perceived “somewhat” appears to him, the perceiving subject. If the perceptum of a subject’s perceptual state was not an existing, or occurring, determinate “somewhat,” then the perceptual state in question (i.e., the “perceiving”) would be a “perception of nothing,” and this is absurd. For, no existing, or occurring, perceptual state is a “perception of nothing.” Furthermore, if the perceptum of a subject’s perceptual state was not itself determinate, then the perceptum would be incapable of appearing to and for the perceiving subject—and this, of course, is absurd. Indeed, unlike an existing, or occurring, determinate “somewhat,” an indeterminate would lack any definite characteristics of its own, and, as such, would not admit to being perceived in any particular way, let alone a variety of ways.However, a perceptual state is determinate only insofar as it terminates in an existing, or occurring, determinate perceptum. Indeed, a perceptual state is what it is (i.e., is determinate and individuated) in virtue of possessing characteristics that are fixed or determined by what the perceptual state is a “perception of.” If this were not so, then it should be possible to render a perceptual state determinable independent of the perceptual state’s objective reference (i.e., without any reference to what it is a “perception of”); however, such a task is impossible not only in practice but in principle. Since no perceptual state can either exist, or occur, unless it is determinate, and a perceptual state is determinate only insofar as its perceptum either exists, or occurs, and is determinate, we are driven to the following result: The Principle of Perceptual Determinacy. According to this principle, for any perceptual state, P, P can neither exist, nor occur, unless P’s perceptum, O, either exists, or occurs, and is determinate.

The Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion

Using the Principle of Perceptual Determinacy, it can be demonstrated that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state either has itself as its own perceptum, or is identical to its own perceptum. In other words, for any existing, or occurring, perceptual state, Pis not a “perception of P.” I call this the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. The following argument illustrates how the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion follows a priori from the Principle of Perceptual Determinacy:
If a perceptual state, A, was a “perception of A,” then A could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, B, that was a “perception of a perception of A.” But could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, E, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, F, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, G, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, H, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” And so on, ad infinitum. We find that neither A, nor any of the aforementioned perceptual states, could either exist, or occur, or be determinate, unless we had reached the end of a vicious regress of perceptual states—and this, of course, is impossible. Therefore, no existing, or occurring, perceptual state either has itself as its own perceptum, or is identical to its own perceptum. Therefore, the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion is true.

The Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability

In a similar vein to the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion, I will introduce what I call the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability. This principle maintains that no n-number (n ≥ 2) existing, or occurring, perceptual states form a series of perceptual states and percepta wherein the first state is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” and so on—the last perceptual state in the series being a “perception of the first.” For clarity, I have provided a list of eight examples of perceptual “loops.”

A Digonal Perceptual “Loop”

Any situation wherein two perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” and the second is a “perception of the first.”

A Trigonal Perceptual “Loop”

Any situation wherein three perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” and the third is a “perception of the first.”

A Tetragonal Perceptual “Loop”

Any situation wherein four perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” and the fourth is a “perception of the first.”

A Pentagonal Perceptual “Loop”

Any situation wherein five perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” and the fifth is a “perception of the first.”

A Hexagonal Perceptual “Loop”

Any situation wherein six perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” the fifth is a “perception of the sixth,” and the sixth is a “perception of the first.” 

A Heptagonal Perceptual “Loop”

Any situation wherein seven perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” the fifth is a “perception of the sixth,” the sixth is a “perception of the seventh,” and the seventh is a “perception of the first.”

An Octagonal Perceptual “Loop”

Any situation wherein eight perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” the fifth is a “perception of the sixth,” the sixth is a “perception of the seventh,” the seventh is a “perception of the eighth,” and the eighth is a “perception of the first.”

And so on, ad indefinitum.

If the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability is true, it would follow that no n-number (n ≥ 2) of existing, or occurring, perceptual states form a series of perceptual states and percepta wherein the first perceptual state in the series is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” and so on—the last perceptual state in the series being a “perception of the first.” Like the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion, the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability follows a priori from the Principle of Perceptual Determinacy. This can be demonstrated by means of the following argument:

If two perceptual states, A and B, were such that was a “perception of B,” and was a “perception of A,” then and could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C, that was a “perception of a perception of B,” and was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D, that was a “perception of a perception of A.” However, and could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, E, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of B,” and was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, F, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of A.” However, and could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, G, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of B,” and F was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, H, that was a “perception of a perception of perception of a perception of A.” And so on, ad infinitum. We find that neither A, nor B, nor any of the aforementioned perceptual states, could either exist, or occur, or be determinate, unless we had reached the end of a vicious regress of perceptual states—and this, of course, is impossible. Therefore, no two existing, or occurring, perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” and the second is a “perception of the first.” Therefore, the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability is true.
One might object by saying that the above argument only demonstrates that a digonal perceptual “loop” can neither exist, nor occur. However, this objection rests on an overlooking the fact that the same conclusion follows if we were to substitute the digonal perceptual “loop” for a trigonal, tetragonal, pentagonal, hexagonal, heptagonal, octagonal (and so on, ad indefinitum) perceptual “loop.” Thus, we can affirm that the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability has been proved.

An Argument Against the Identity Theory of Mind

Let’s imagine two neighbors: John and Thomas. If John were to have a perceptual state, A, and A was a “perception of Thomas’s perceptual state, B,” and if Thomas’s perceptual state, B, was a “perception of John’s perceptual state, A,” then John’s and Thomas’s perceptual states would form a digonal perceptual “loop.” However, since we have proved the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability, it follows that such a digonal perceptual “loop” can neither exist, nor occur. Therefore, if John were to have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, A, and A was a “perception of Thomas’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, B,” then Thomas’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, B, cannot—on pain of contradiction—be a “perception of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, A.”

According to the Identity Theory, all of John’s perceptual states are identical to some of John’s brain states, and all of Thomas’s perceptual states are identical to some of Thomas’s brain states. In other words, if John were to have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, A, then A would be identical to John’s existing, or occurring, brain state, θ, and if Thomas were to have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state B, then would be identical to Thomas’s existing, or occurring, brain state, ψ. Furthermore, since the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability is true, we arrive at the following result: 

If the Identity Theory is true, then if John has an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, A, and A is a “perception of Thomas’s existing, or occurring, brain state, ψ,” then Thomas’s existing, or occurring, brain state, ψ, cannot—on pain of contradiction—be a “perception of John’s existing, or occurring, brain state, θ.”

Now, there is nothing absurd or contradictory in the idea that John can perceive (i) any of his own existing, or occurring, brain states, and (ii) any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas perceives any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain. Likewise, there is nothing unintelligible or self-contradictory in the idea that Thomas can perceive (i) any of his own existing, or occurring, brain states, and (ii) any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain whilst John perceives any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain. Indeed, we must admit that it is possible—in principle—for John to perceive (i) any of his own existing, or occurring, brain states, and (ii) any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas perceives any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain. Again, we must also admit that it is possible—in principle—for Thomas to perceive (i) any of his own existing, or occurring, brain states, and (ii) any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain whilst John perceives any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain. However, if the Identity Theory is true, then it would be a contradiction for John to perceive a certain existing, or occurring, state, ψ, of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas is perceiving a certain existing, or occurring, state, θ, of John’s brain. Indeed, such a state of affairs would be impossible—in principle. Therefore, since it is possible—in principle—for John to perceive any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas perceives any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain, it follows that the Identity Theory is false. We may put the general argument in the following form:

P1)  If the Identity Theory is true, then John cannot—in principle—perceive any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas perceives any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain.
P2)  John can—in principle—perceive any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas perceives any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain.
C1)  Therefore, the Identity Theory is false. [From P1 and P2]
We may transpose the above argument in a way that focuses solely on John. This variation of the argument relies solely on Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion without relying on the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability. The Identity Theory, as we have seen, is committed to John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, being identical to one of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states (at the time of John’s having of the perceptual state, P). Since the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion is true, it follows that whenever John has an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, P’s perceptum, O, cannot—in principle—be John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P. However, it follows from this that if it is possible—in principle—for John to have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, that is a “perception of” any one of his existing, or occurring, brain states (at the time of John’s having of the perceptual state, P), then John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, is not identical to any one of his existing, or occurring, brain states (at the time of John’s having of the perceptual state, P). But if John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, is not identical to any one of his existing, or occurring, brain states (at the time of John’s having of the perceptual state, P), it follows that the Identity Theory is false; for, such a theory is committed to John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, being identical to one of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states (at the time of John’s having of the perceptual state, P). Since it is possible—in principle—for John to have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, that is a “perception of” any one of his existing, or occurring, brain states (at the time of John’s having of the perceptual state, P), it follows that the Identity Theory is false. We may standardize the argument as follows:

P1)  If the Identity Theory is true, then all of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states are identical to some of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states.
P2)  If all of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states are identical to some of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states, then some of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states cannot—in principle—be the percepta of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states. 
P3)  All of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states can—in principle—be the percepta of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states. 
C1)  Therefore, the Identity Theory is false. [From P1—P3]
The Identity Theorist cannot reject the argument’s first premise without giving up the Identity Theory, and the Identity Theorist cannot challenge the second premise without first refuting the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion—something which I take to have been sufficiently proved. Furthermore, the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion follows a priori from the Principle of Perceptual Determinacy. Therefore, in order for the Identity Theorist to reject the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion, he must first reject the Principle of Perceptual Determinacy. With respect to the third premise, there is clearly nothing absurd or contradictory involved in the idea that John can—in principle—perceive any given existing, or occurring, state of his own brain whilst having an existing, or occurring, perceptual state. Indeed, if John’s optic nerves were lengthened and his eyes positioned correctly, he would certainly be able to perceive his own brain states (Not to mention the possibility of John using an autocerebroscope to perceive his brain states).Now, suppose the Identity Theorist were to argue that whenever a perceptual state (or a brain state) is perceived, it cannot be perceived in its entirety, but only partially, thus a perceptual state (or a brain state) having itself as its own perceptum would present no difficulty. Such an objection fails because it would lead to the following contradiction: a proper part of a whole (i.e., the perceived part of the whole perceptual state) would be both less than, and identical to, the whole (i.e., the whole perceptual state) of which it was a proper part.

Now, there is a third argument that we may employ against the Identity Theory that makes use of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion and the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability—both of which follow a priori from the Principle of Perceptual Determinacy. The argument takes the following form:
P1)  If the Identity Theory is true, then there are some brain states which are—in principle—imperceptible. 
P2)  There are no brain states which are—in principle—imperceptible. 
C1)  Therefore, the Identity Theory is false. [From P1 and P2]
As mentioned in the preceding paragraphs, there is nothing at all incoherent or contradictory in the idea that all existing, or occurring, brain states are—in principle—perceptible; indeed, it seems that it is not only possible in theory, but also—eventually—in practice.As the force of the argument lies in the first premise, I will concentrate my attention on defending it the most.  The first premise is based on the fact that if the Identity Theory is true, then all existing, or occurring, perceptual states are identical to some existing, or occurring, brain states. Supposing that all existing, or occurring, perceptual states are identical to some existing, or occurring, brain states, it can be demonstrated that there are some existing, or occurring, brain states which are—in principle—imperceptible. The argument is as follows:
If an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, A, is a “perception of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, B,” then is neither the perceptum of B, nor the perceptum of A; because if was the perceptum of either or B, then either the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion, or the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability would be violated. However, this entails that is imperceptible—in principle—unless was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C,—a perceptual state that was different from and B.
Indeed, if was the perceptum of A, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if was the perceptum of B, then we would have a digonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability. 
However, this entails that is imperceptible—in principle—unless was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D,—a perceptual state that was different from AB, and C.
Indeed, if was the perceptum of C, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if was the perceptum of either or B, then we would have either a digonal, or trigonal, perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability. 
However, this entails that D is imperceptible—in principle—unless D was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, E,—a perceptual state that was different from ABC, and D.
Indeed, if was the perceptum of D, then we would have an existing or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if was the perceptum of either AB, or C, then we would have either a digonal, trigonal, or tetragonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability. 
However, this entails that is imperceptible—in principle—unless was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, F,—a perceptual state that was different from ABCD, and E.
Indeed, if was the perceptum of E, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if was the perceptum of either ABC, or D, then we would have either a digonal, trigonal, tetragonal, or pentagonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability. 
However, this entails that is imperceptible—in principle—unless was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, G,—a perceptual state that was different from ABCDE, and F.
Indeed, if was the perceptum of F, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if was the perceptum of either ABCD, or E, then we would have either a digonal, trigonal, tetragonal, pentagonal, or hexagonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability.
And so on, ad infinitum.
We are forced into a vicious infinite regress. Every new existing, or occurring, perceptual state needing to be posited to account for another perceptual state’s imperceptibility would itself be imperceptible—in principle—unless another existing, or occurring, perceptual state were posited; however, this existing, or occurring, perceptual state would itself be imperceptible—in principle—unless another existing, or occurring, perceptual state were posited, and so on, ad infinitum. Therefore, since the regress is vicious, it follows that there are some existing, or occurring, perceptual states which are—in principle—imperceptible. However, this means that if all existing, or occurring perceptual states are identical to some existing, or occurring, brain states, then some existing, or occurring, brain states are—in principle—imperceptible. But, as we saw above, all existing, or occurring, brain states are—in principle—perceptible. Therefore, it follows that some existing, or occurring, perceptual states are not brain states. Since the truth of the Identity Theory rests upon all existing, or occurring, perceptual states being identical to some existing, or occurring, brain states, it follows that the Identity Theory is false.
 
I have provided a diagram illustrating the vicious regress and the two-horned dilemma which follows from it. Each of the circles represent a particular perceptual state (e.g., Perceptual State A, Perceptual State B, Perceptual State C, Perceptual State D, Perceptual State E, and Perceptual State F). If a circle is green, then said perceptual state is the perceptum of another perceptual state (i.e., It is perceived). If a circle is red, then said perceptual state is not the perceptum of another perceptual state (i.e., The perceptual state is imperceptible). A black arrow pointing from one perceptual state to another perceptual state signifies that the former perceptual state is a perception of the latter perceptual state (e.g., The black arrow pointing from Perceptual State to Perceptual State signifies that Perceptual State is a perception of Perceptual State B). A red arrow pointing from one perceptual state to another perceptual state signifies that the former perceptual state is not, and cannot be, a perception of the latter perceptual state—on pain of violating the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion (e.g., The red arrow pointing from Perceptual State to Perceptual State signifies that Perceptual State is not, and cannot be, a perception of Perceptual State A—on pain of violating the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion). Perceptual situations contained in red boxes violate either the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion (e.g., Fig. 1) or the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability (e.g., Fig. 3, Fig. 5, and Fig. 7). Perceptual situations contained in green boxes neither violate the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion, nor the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability; however, in such perceptual situations, there is always a remaining perceptual state—an imperceptible one—that is left unaccounted for (e.g., Fig. 2, Fig. 4, Fig. 6, and Fig. 8).

Addressing Two Objections

First Objection

“I wondered why one couldn’t perceive the contents of perception at different times. Perhaps when a tree is the perceptum of a perceptual state (brain state B), I could later have a new perceptual state to perceive brain state B. Then all the brain states would still be perceptible in principle.”

My concern with the proposed solution is that it faces the same dilemma that would arise if the perceptual states were simultaneous. Let me try to illustrate the issue:
If an existing, or occurring, perceptual state A was a “perception of a perceptual state, B,” and had either existed, or occurred, prior to A, then could have neither been the perceptum of (since hadn’t even existed yet to be the perceptum of B), nor could have been the perceptum of (without violating the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion). However, it follows from this that would be imperceptible—in principle—unless it was the perceptum of another existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C,—a perceptual state that was itself different from and B. Now, it is clear that if either existed, or occurred, later than and B, then could have neither been the perceptum of A, nor the perceptum of (since hadn’t even existed yet to be the perceptum of either or B). However, if was the perceptum of C, then the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion would have been violated. Thus, would be imperceptible—in principle—unless it was the perceptum of another existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D,—a perceptual state that was different from AB, and C. And so on, ad infinitum.
Just as before, every new existing, or occurring, perceptual state needing to be posited to account for another perceptual state’s imperceptibility would itself be imperceptible—in principle—unless another existing, or occurring, perceptual state were posited; however, this existing, or occurring, perceptual state would itself be imperceptible—in principle—unless another existing, or occurring, perceptual state were posited, and so on, ad infinitum. In short, no matter how many perceptual states we posit, we will always get stuck with a “imperceptible” remainder left unaccounted for.

Second Objection

“If I follow, the core point is that a perceptual state’s character is inherited by its perceptum—the object of the perceptual state (q.v. The Principle of Perceptual Determinacy); and since a perceptual state’s character is “fixed” or rendered determinate by its perceptum, it follows that the perceptum of a perceptual state must have a character independent of that perceptual state. From this it seems to follow that (i) a perceptual state cannot be a “perception of itself” (q.v. The Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion), (ii) no two perceptual states can be of one another, and (iii) no n-number (n ≥ 2) of perceptual states can form a series of perceptual states and percepta wherein the first perceptual state in the series is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” and so on—the last perceptual state in the series being a “perception of the first.”  (q.v. The Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability).

 

However, if the Identity Theory is true, and all perceptual states are identical to some brain states, then it is possible—in principle—for a perceptual state to be a “perception of itself”; indeed, it is possible—in principle—for someone to have a perceptual state of any of their brain states. For consider, a person can perceive any of their brain states (a) in a mirror, (b) by having their optic nerves surgically extended—a medical operation which, if not capable of being performed with today’s technology, is by no means incapable of being accomplished in the near future, or even (c) by means of Feigl’s hypothetical autocerebroscope. Furthermore, if the Identity Theory is true, and all perceptual states are identical to some brain states, then it is possible—in principle—for two perceptual states to be of one another; indeed, it is possible—in principle—for two craniotomy patients to be positioned in such a way so that they perceive one another’s brain states simultaneously. Likewise, if the Identity Theory is true, then it is possible—in principle—for n-number (n ≥ 2) of perceptual states to form a series of perceptual states and percepta wherein the first perceptual state in the series is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” and so on—the last perceptual state in the series being a “perception of the first.” Indeed, like before with two craniotomy patients, it is possible—in principle—for n-number (n ≥ 2) of craniotomy patients to be arranged in such a way that the first patient in the group perceives any one of the brain states of a second patient, the second perceives any one of the brain states of the third, the third perceives any one of the brain states of the fourth, and so on—the last patient in the group perceiving any one of the first patient’s brain states. Therefore, the Identity Theory is false.


It seems to me that the best reply for an Identity Theorist would probably be to say that it is not true that a perceptual state inherits its character from its object. Rather, a perceptual state represents an object/character that may or may not exist. And so, there is no problem with a perceptual state being of itself, any more than there is a problem with other cases of reflective representation (e.g., the novel, Don Quixote, is, in part, about the novel, Don Quixote).”


There appear to be a couple of difficulties entailed by this suggested response. My first concern is that there seems to be a serious dilemma when it comes to the self-representation involved in a perceptual state having itself as its own perceptum. Coincidentally, A.E. Taylor’s criticism of Josiah Royce’s conception of the Absolute as a self-representing system parallels the issues involved in the actual implementation of a perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum:
“Professor Royce’s own illustration of the map of England executed upon a portion of the surface of the country is really a typical instance of a self-contradictory purpose. He argues that such a map, to be theoretically perfect, must contain a reduced facsimile of itself as part of the country mapped, and this again another, and so on indefinitely. But the whole force of the reasoning depends on overlooking the distinction between the surface of England as it is before the map is made, and the surface of England as altered by the presence of the map. Prof. Royce assumes that you set out to represent in the map a state of things which can in fact have no existence until after the map is made. The previous existence of the map at a certain spot is falsely taken to be one of the conditions to which the map-maker is to conform in executing it. Every one of the supposed “maps within the map” will thus involve distortion and misrepresentation of the district it proposes to map. It is as if Hamlet had chosen “Hamlet” as the subject of the “play within the play.” The professor’s illustration thus does less than justice to his theory.” (Taylor, Elements of Metaphysics, 150)
My second concern is that the proposed objection (i.e., that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state has any of its characteristics determined by the characteristics of its perceptum) ends up vindicating the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion—the very principle the objection sought to dissolve. The self-undermining character of the proposed objection can be made more explicit with the help from the following argument (an argument inspired by J.M.E. McTaggart’s conception of “Intrinsic Determination” as a relation between characteristics):

Let X represent the characteristic of “having the characteristic of ‘neither existing, nor occurring, if perceptual state, P, neither exists, nor occurs’.”  
Let Y represent the characteristic of “neither existing, nor occurring, if perceptual state, P, neither exists, nor occurs.” 
Now, the occurrence of X as a characteristic in a given thing “intrinsically determines” the occurrence of Y as a characteristic in a given thing because the proposition “something has the characteristic X” implies the proposition “something has the characteristic Y.” As a matter of fact, the occurrence of X as a characteristic in a given thing determines the occurrence of Y as a characteristic in that very same thing which possesses X as a characteristic.  
Now, if an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has none of its characteristics determined by any of the characteristics of its perceptum, then it immediately follows that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has itself as its own perceptum. This can be demonstrated in the following manner: 
If an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, had itself as its own perceptum, then P’s perceptum would have the characteristic of “having the characteristic of ‘neither existing, nor occurring, if P neither exists, nor occurs’.” However, the “having” of this characteristic by P’s perceptum would thereby determine the occurrence of the characteristic of “neither existing, nor occurring, if P neither exists, nor occurs,” in P’s perceptum. However, ex hypothesiP’s perceptum is P itself. Thus, X being a characteristic of P’s perceptum would intrinsically determine Y as a characteristic of P. In other words, if no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has any of its characteristics determined by the characteristics of its perceptum, it follows that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has itself as its own perceptum. And since the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion holds that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has itself as its own perceptum, it follows that the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion is true.
The proposed objection to our argument (i.e., that no existing or occurring perceptual state has any of its characteristics determined by the characteristics of its perceptum) has thus ended up vindicating the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion.

If the preceding arguments are sound, then the Identity Theory of Mind would have been refuted—refuted not by an appeal to the apparent qualitative character of our subjective life, but through an analysis of the hidden implications embedded in the very conditions that must be satisfied in order for perceptual states and their percepta to either exist or occur.

Footnotes

[1] If the argument does succeed, then the Identity Theory of Mind (both the “token-identity” and “type-identity” theories) will not be the only view that is refuted. Indeed, since the Functionalist maintains, with the Identity Theorist, that every individual mental state or event is identical with some physiological state or event, it follows that (physicalistic) Functionalism would be refuted by this argument as well.

[2] The italicized “is” should be interpreted as the “is” of identity. Thus, for any perceptual state, P, P is identical to a “perception of a perceptum, O.”

[3] Just as every perceptual state has a correlative perceptum, so too does every perceptum have a corresponding perceptual state. Thus, for any perceptum, O, there is a particular “somewhat” which is identical to the “perception ofthat perceptum, O.

[4] Further, it is important to note that a perceptual state’s perceptum needn’t be perceived accurately for it to be the perceptual state’s perceptum. Suppose that (i) a perceptual state, A, is a “perception of a “somewhat” as having property f,” and (ii) there just so happens to be no existent, or occurrent, “somewhat,” that has property f. Although A’s perceptum is perceived as having properties that it does not, in fact, have (i.e., the property f), it does not follow that A’s perceptum (i.e., the particular “somewhat” which is erroneously perceived as having property f) neither exists, nor occurs, nor is determinate. On the contrary, just as perceptual state A exists, or occurs, and is determinate, A’s perceptum exists, or occurs, and is determinate—the perceptum is simply misperceived or erroneously perceived. Cf. “Objects have an indefinite number of characteristics….It is a logically necessary truth that if a physical object exists it is determinate in all its characteristics….The objects and properties of objects that are immediately perceived have an existence logically independent of their being perceived. There are objects and properties of objects that are never perceived, although it would always be logically possible for such unperceived things to be perceived.” (Armstrong, Perception and the Physical World, 25, 60, 192) 

[5] And these possibilities (e.g., that it is possible—in principle—for someone to have a perceptual state of any of their brain states) have even been accepted by Identity Theorists like William Lycan (someone who hasn’t seen this argument). Indeed, in an interview, Lycan states that “according to me, you can certainly perceive the thing [i.e., the brain state] that is your own perceptual state if you have autocerebroscope and were looking at your own brain….I am assuming, of course, something controversial—that a perceptual state is a brain state and nothing more. Therefore, if you have an autocerebroscope, and you turn it on your own brain, you can perceive that state. You won’t perceive it as a perception, you'll perceive it as “brain stuff,” but the thing you’re perceiving is that state.” (Lycan, Friction: Epistemology, Mind, 2021-08-17”) We also see something similar in Herbert Feigl’s writings: “Just as one’s eyes are not a part of one’s visual field...so is one’s brain (without the aid of an autocerebroscope) not part of the world perceived” (Feigl, Some Crucial Issues of Mind-Body Monism, 306) [The italics are mine] Thus, Feigl (a proponent of the Identity Theory) would agree that it is perfectly conceivable that John could—in principle—perceive any given state of his own brain. We find something similar in the writings of the idealist W.J. Mander: “We have a least a partial experience of our own bodies, but we do not generally perceive our brains at all. It is clear, however, that that is not impossible. It is merely contingent that we do not do so. The following science-fiction thought-experiment makes this plain enough. Suppose that in the future we found it advantageous (perhaps for security reasons) to take our brains out of our bodies, and keep them in a vat of nutrient fluid, connecting them to our body’s nervous system by wi-fi. In such a case it would be possible for me to examine my own brain as it lay sitting before me on the desk. My own brain would become one more among the many other objects within my experience. I could see it, touch it, or smell it, as well as apply to it more sophisticated modes of perceptual extension, such as monitoring its blood flow levels or recording its electro-chemical activity.” (Mander, Idealism, Narrative and the Mind-Brain Relation, 2)

[6] Now, “perceptible-in-principle” and “imperceptible-in-principle,” like “knowable-in-principle,” are, in fact, genuine or “extensional” properties, rather than merely “intensional” properties. The fact that “perceptible-in-principle” and “imperceptible-in-principle” are extensional properties renders the preceding argument immune from accusations of committing a “masked-man” or “intensional” fallacy.