“He sees, but he can’t be seen, he hears, but he can’t be heard; he thinks, but he can’t be thought of; he perceives, but he can’t be perceived.”
Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upanishad, 3.7.23
The Principle of Perceptual Determinacy
The Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion
If a perceptual state, A, was a “perception of A,” then A could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, B, that was a “perception of a perception of A.” But B could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But C could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But D could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, E, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But E could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, F, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But F could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, G, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” But G could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless it was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, H, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of A.” And so on, ad infinitum. We find that neither A, nor any of the aforementioned perceptual states, could either exist, or occur, or be determinate, unless we had reached the end of a vicious regress of perceptual states—and this, of course, is impossible. Therefore, no existing, or occurring, perceptual state either has itself as its own perceptum, or is identical to its own perceptum. Therefore, the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion is true.
The Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability
A Digonal Perceptual “Loop”
Any situation wherein two perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” and the second is a “perception of the first.”A Trigonal Perceptual “Loop”
Any situation wherein three perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” and the third is a “perception of the first.”A Tetragonal Perceptual “Loop”
Any situation wherein four perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” and the fourth is a “perception of the first.”A Pentagonal Perceptual “Loop”
Any situation wherein five perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” and the fifth is a “perception of the first.”A Hexagonal Perceptual “Loop”
Any situation wherein six perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” the fifth is a “perception of the sixth,” and the sixth is a “perception of the first.”A Heptagonal Perceptual “Loop”
Any situation wherein seven perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” the fifth is a “perception of the sixth,” the sixth is a “perception of the seventh,” and the seventh is a “perception of the first.”An Octagonal Perceptual “Loop”
Any situation wherein eight perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” the fourth is a “perception of the fifth,” the fifth is a “perception of the sixth,” the sixth is a “perception of the seventh,” the seventh is a “perception of the eighth,” and the eighth is a “perception of the first.”And so on, ad indefinitum.
If two perceptual states, A and B, were such that A was a “perception of B,” and B was a “perception of A,” then A and B could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless A was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C, that was a “perception of a perception of B,” and B was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D, that was a “perception of a perception of A.” However, C and D could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless C was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, E, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of B,” and D was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, F, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of A.” However, E and F could neither exist, nor occur, nor be determinate, unless E was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, G, that was a “perception of a perception of a perception of a perception of B,” and F was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, H, that was a “perception of a perception of perception of a perception of A.” And so on, ad infinitum. We find that neither A, nor B, nor any of the aforementioned perceptual states, could either exist, or occur, or be determinate, unless we had reached the end of a vicious regress of perceptual states—and this, of course, is impossible. Therefore, no two existing, or occurring, perceptual states are such that the first is a “perception of the second,” and the second is a “perception of the first.” Therefore, the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability is true.
An Argument Against the Identity Theory of Mind
If the Identity Theory is true, then if John has an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, A, and A is a “perception of Thomas’s existing, or occurring, brain state, ψ,” then Thomas’s existing, or occurring, brain state, ψ, cannot—on pain of contradiction—be a “perception of John’s existing, or occurring, brain state, θ.”
P1) If the Identity Theory is true, then John cannot—in principle—perceive any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas perceives any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain.
P2) John can—in principle—perceive any existing, or occurring, state of Thomas’s brain whilst Thomas perceives any existing, or occurring, state of John’s brain.
C1) Therefore, the Identity Theory is false. [From P1 and P2]
P1) If the Identity Theory is true, then all of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states are identical to some of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states.
P2) If all of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states are identical to some of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states, then some of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states cannot—in principle—be the percepta of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states.
P3) All of John’s existing, or occurring, brain states can—in principle—be the percepta of John’s existing, or occurring, perceptual states.
C1) Therefore, the Identity Theory is false. [From P1—P3]
P1) If the Identity Theory is true, then there are some brain states which are—in principle—imperceptible.
P2) There are no brain states which are—in principle—imperceptible.
C1) Therefore, the Identity Theory is false. [From P1 and P2]
If an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, A, is a “perception of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, B,” then A is neither the perceptum of B, nor the perceptum of A; because if A was the perceptum of either A or B, then either the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion, or the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability would be violated. However, this entails that A is imperceptible—in principle—unless A was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C,—a perceptual state that was different from A and B.Indeed, if A was the perceptum of A, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if A was the perceptum of B, then we would have a digonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability.However, this entails that C is imperceptible—in principle—unless C was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D,—a perceptual state that was different from A, B, and C.Indeed, if C was the perceptum of C, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if C was the perceptum of either A or B, then we would have either a digonal, or trigonal, perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability.However, this entails that D is imperceptible—in principle—unless D was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, E,—a perceptual state that was different from A, B, C, and D.Indeed, if D was the perceptum of D, then we would have an existing or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if D was the perceptum of either A, B, or C, then we would have either a digonal, trigonal, or tetragonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability.However, this entails that E is imperceptible—in principle—unless E was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, F,—a perceptual state that was different from A, B, C, D, and E.Indeed, if E was the perceptum of E, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if E was the perceptum of either A, B, C, or D, then we would have either a digonal, trigonal, tetragonal, or pentagonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability.However, this entails that F is imperceptible—in principle—unless F was the perceptum of an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, G,—a perceptual state that was different from A, B, C, D, E, and F.Indeed, if F was the perceptum of F, then we would have an existing, or occurring, perceptual state that had itself as its own perceptum—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion. Furthermore, if F was the perceptum of either A, B, C, D, or E, then we would have either a digonal, trigonal, tetragonal, pentagonal, or hexagonal perceptual “loop”—a clear violation of the Principle of Perceptual Non-Loopability.And so on, ad infinitum.
Addressing Two Objections
First Objection
“I wondered why one couldn’t perceive the contents of perception at different times. Perhaps when a tree is the perceptum of a perceptual state (brain state B), I could later have a new perceptual state to perceive brain state B. Then all the brain states would still be perceptible in principle.”
If an existing, or occurring, perceptual state A was a “perception of a perceptual state, B,” and B had either existed, or occurred, prior to A, then A could have neither been the perceptum of B (since A hadn’t even existed yet to be the perceptum of B), nor could A have been the perceptum of A (without violating the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion). However, it follows from this that A would be imperceptible—in principle—unless it was the perceptum of another existing, or occurring, perceptual state, C,—a perceptual state that was itself different from A and B. Now, it is clear that if C either existed, or occurred, later than A and B, then C could have neither been the perceptum of A, nor the perceptum of B (since C hadn’t even existed yet to be the perceptum of either A or B). However, if C was the perceptum of C, then the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion would have been violated. Thus, C would be imperceptible—in principle—unless it was the perceptum of another existing, or occurring, perceptual state, D,—a perceptual state that was different from A, B, and C. And so on, ad infinitum.
Second Objection
“If
I follow, the core point is that a perceptual state’s character is inherited by
its perceptum—the object of the perceptual state
(q.v. The Principle of Perceptual Determinacy); and since a perceptual
state’s character is “fixed” or rendered determinate by its perceptum, it
follows that the perceptum of a perceptual state must have a character
independent of that perceptual state. From this it seems to follow that (i) a perceptual
state cannot be a “perception of itself” (q.v. The Principle of
Perceptual Self-Exclusion), (ii) no two perceptual states can be of one
another, and (iii) no n-number (n
≥ 2) of perceptual states can form a series of perceptual states and
percepta wherein the first perceptual state in the series is a “perception of the second,” the second is a
“perception of the third,”
the third is a “perception of the
fourth,” and so on—the last perceptual state in the series being a “perception of the first.” (q.v. The Principle of Perceptual
Non-Loopability).
However, if the Identity Theory is true, and all perceptual states are identical to some brain states, then it is possible—in principle—for a perceptual state to be a “perception of itself”; indeed, it is possible—in principle—for someone to have a perceptual state of any of their brain states. For consider, a person can perceive any of their brain states (a) in a mirror, (b) by having their optic nerves surgically extended—a medical operation which, if not capable of being performed with today’s technology, is by no means incapable of being accomplished in the near future, or even (c) by means of Feigl’s hypothetical autocerebroscope. Furthermore, if the Identity Theory is true, and all perceptual states are identical to some brain states, then it is possible—in principle—for two perceptual states to be of one another; indeed, it is possible—in principle—for two craniotomy patients to be positioned in such a way so that they perceive one another’s brain states simultaneously. Likewise, if the Identity Theory is true, then it is possible—in principle—for n-number (n ≥ 2) of perceptual states to form a series of perceptual states and percepta wherein the first perceptual state in the series is a “perception of the second,” the second is a “perception of the third,” the third is a “perception of the fourth,” and so on—the last perceptual state in the series being a “perception of the first.” Indeed, like before with two craniotomy patients, it is possible—in principle—for n-number (n ≥ 2) of craniotomy patients to be arranged in such a way that the first patient in the group perceives any one of the brain states of a second patient, the second perceives any one of the brain states of the third, the third perceives any one of the brain states of the fourth, and so on—the last patient in the group perceiving any one of the first patient’s brain states. Therefore, the Identity Theory is false.
It seems to me that the best reply for an Identity Theorist would probably be to say that it is not true that a perceptual state inherits its character from its object. Rather, a perceptual state represents an object/character that may or may not exist. And so, there is no problem with a perceptual state being of itself, any more than there is a problem with other cases of reflective representation (e.g., the novel, Don Quixote, is, in part, about the novel, Don Quixote).”
“Professor Royce’s own illustration of the map of England executed upon a portion of the surface of the country is really a typical instance of a self-contradictory purpose. He argues that such a map, to be theoretically perfect, must contain a reduced facsimile of itself as part of the country mapped, and this again another, and so on indefinitely. But the whole force of the reasoning depends on overlooking the distinction between the surface of England as it is before the map is made, and the surface of England as altered by the presence of the map. Prof. Royce assumes that you set out to represent in the map a state of things which can in fact have no existence until after the map is made. The previous existence of the map at a certain spot is falsely taken to be one of the conditions to which the map-maker is to conform in executing it. Every one of the supposed “maps within the map” will thus involve distortion and misrepresentation of the district it proposes to map. It is as if Hamlet had chosen “Hamlet” as the subject of the “play within the play.” The professor’s illustration thus does less than justice to his theory.” (Taylor, Elements of Metaphysics, 150)
Let X represent the characteristic of “having the characteristic of ‘neither existing, nor occurring, if perceptual state, P, neither exists, nor occurs’.”
Let Y represent the characteristic of “neither existing, nor occurring, if perceptual state, P, neither exists, nor occurs.”
Now, the occurrence of X as a characteristic in a given thing “intrinsically determines” the occurrence of Y as a characteristic in a given thing because the proposition “something has the characteristic X” implies the proposition “something has the characteristic Y.” As a matter of fact, the occurrence of X as a characteristic in a given thing determines the occurrence of Y as a characteristic in that very same thing which possesses X as a characteristic.
Now, if an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has none of its characteristics determined by any of the characteristics of its perceptum, then it immediately follows that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has itself as its own perceptum. This can be demonstrated in the following manner:If an existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, had itself as its own perceptum, then P’s perceptum would have the characteristic of “having the characteristic of ‘neither existing, nor occurring, if P neither exists, nor occurs’.” However, the “having” of this characteristic by P’s perceptum would thereby determine the occurrence of the characteristic of “neither existing, nor occurring, if P neither exists, nor occurs,” in P’s perceptum. However, ex hypothesi, P’s perceptum is P itself. Thus, X being a characteristic of P’s perceptum would intrinsically determine Y as a characteristic of P. In other words, if no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has any of its characteristics determined by the characteristics of its perceptum, it follows that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has itself as its own perceptum. And since the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion holds that no existing, or occurring, perceptual state, P, has itself as its own perceptum, it follows that the Principle of Perceptual Self-Exclusion is true.
Footnotes
Looks interesting. I wondered why one couldn't perceive the contents of perception *at different times*. Like maybe when a tree image is a content of a visual perception (brain state B), I could later have a new perception to be aware of brain state B. Then all the brain sates would still be perceptible in principle.
ReplyDeleteI also wondered why you would need such an elaborate argument. Here is a simpler one:
1. A blue image is sometimes the content of a perceptual experience.
2. A blue image is never the content of a brain state. (The neuroscientists never found blue images in brains.)
3. Therefore, a perceptual experience is not a brain state.
Thank you so much for your reply, Dr. Rasmussen! I’ll try to reply to it in detail tomorrow!
DeleteDear Dr. Rasmussen, I replied to your comment in the following post: https://thepessimisticidealist.blogspot.com/2022/04/addressing-another-reply-to-argument.html
Delete